(I)
The Structure of the Post-war System:
The UN Charter as the
Embodiment of the "Spirit of 1945"
In 1945, the founders of the United Nations envisaged an international
order to be guaranteed by the victorious powers of World War II. For half
a century the world organization has been tied to the power balance of
1945. Any question of UN reform therefore has to address the question as
to whether the global constellation at the turn of the millennium is still
the same as when the organization was founded, and if not, in what respect
( or in what direction ( it has changed. Common sense tells us that after
the end of the bipolar system of the Cold War and since the emergence of
new regional powers that did not yet exist as sovereign entities when the
United Nations Organization was founded, a completely new scene of international
actors has arisen, one which must be assessed with regard to each country's
right to be adequately represented in the international decision-making
processes.
It goes without saying that a Charter which suits the interests of a
small minority of member states (as those interests were defined in 1945) cannot
be sacrosanct under circumstances in which the organization increasingly assumes
a universal character with regard to its membership, in contrast to its founding
period, when it was merely a minority organization of certain colonial powers
and their allies in a peculiar constellation that had emerged from a world war.
Article 107 of the UN Charter clearly documents this legacy of a global armed
confrontation. If a system that is the result of such a historical struggle is
preserved under totally different circumstances (whether economic, political or
military) one may well raise the question as to whether this will not further
intensify tensions and injustices on the global level, contrary to the aims and
purposes as proclaimed in the Charter itself.
The central problem with regard to this World War II legacy is definitely
the structure and authority of the Security Council in the constitutional
framework of the Charter. The present UN system vests practically unlimited
power in the victors of World War II, the permanent members of the Security
Council, and allows the General Assembly only to play a marginal role.
This system does not meet even the basic requirements of the international
rule of law, as no separation of powers exists under the UN Charter. The
Security Council exercises de facto supreme legislative and executive powers
(and even judicial powers). This has been evidenced in the recent sanctions
resolutions against Libya.1 Because of the special Charter provision in
Art. 12, the Council can effectively block any deliberations by the General
Assembly (which is not in itself a genuinely democratic body, either).
The "Uniting for Peace Resolution" which is often referred to
by idealistic believers in the UN system does not give adequate redress
to this disquieting situation of Security Council domination over the agenda
of the General Assembly.2 On the basis of an excessive interpretation of
the respective provisions of Chapter VII, particularly Art. 42, the Security
Council further reserves for itself the right to declare and to wage (or "authorize") war with impunity. This was demonstrated beyond
any doubt in the case of the Gulf Conflict of 1990-1991, in which the actual
warfare authorized by the Council far exceeded the stated purpose of restoring
the sovereignty of Kuwait.3
Furthermore, the veto privilege of the permanent members is not only
incompatible with basic principles of transnational democracy; it is tantamount
to the traditional jus ad bellum (long abandoned in the doctrine of international
law) because it allows for the reintroduction of the concept of "just
war," i.e. of waging aggression under the protection of a kind of
"legal immunity" which is practically granted to the permanent
members because of specific procedural rules contained in Art. 27 of the
Charter.4
Vague provisions in the UN Charter have allowed the Security Council
(particularly since the collapse of the Soviet Union and the end of the
East-West conflict) to gradually arrogate additional powers beyond its original
mandate and in contradiction with general rules of international law. We have
seen this in the adjudication of border disputes (as in the case of Iraq and
Kuwait) and in the setting up of international tribunals (as in the cases of
former Yugoslavia and Rwanda). All of this is clearly in violation of the
principles of the separation of powers ( so essential for the rule of law (and
to the detriment of the status and competence of the International Court of
Justice). The domineering nature of the Security Council's role in the UN power
equation which was designed to suit the
Allied Powers of World War II is even more
serious and detrimental to global justice at a time when only one superpower
determines the course of action.
All of the above-mentioned forms of an unrestrained and uncontrolled
exercise of power resemble the traditional system of government as represented
by European absolutism. This kind of unrestricted rule is the direct result
of a change in the balance of power since the end of the East-West conflict.
The effective control of the only remaining superpower over the decision-making
processes of the Security Council has led to an erosion of international
legitimacy and has severely undermined the UN Charter in its basic claim
of establishing an international order where peace and human rights prevail.
Under the slogan of the "New World Order," a policy of double
standards has been introduced in the international arena, where interests
prevail over rights of peoples and states.5 A striking example of this
trend is the recent sanctions policy and practice of the Security Council.6
This factual situation reveals the basic weaknesses of the UN system
with regard to the requirements of transnational democracy. An organization
whose charter deliberately excludes any regulations of checks and balances
and enthrones the victorious powers of World War II as custodians of humanity
(in the political, legal and ethical meaning of the term) necessarily falls
victim to the only remaining superpower, which then alone benefits from
the de facto-immunity it enjoys under the Security Council's procedural
rules which were originally designed by the victors of World War II to
ensure their permanent control over world affairs and over the world organization.
The developments since Gulf War II (1991) have made this even more evident.
If we take all these factors into due consideration, we realize that
there is no true international legitimacy in the present global constellation.
Any decision about international peace and security
especially on the
basis of Chapter VII of the Charter is determined by the interests of
particular UN member states, which override the interests of the weaker
states. The UN Charter with its provisions in favour of a strong Security
Council that is to say, its permanent members
serves as a convenient
cover for old-fashioned realpolitik, whether in the Gulf, in Somalia, in
former Yugoslavia, etc. Because of the lack of mechanisms of democratic
control in the Charter itself, the most powerful state is able in many
instances to have its interests "canonized." Smaller states are
involuntarily reduced to the status of puppets that can do no more than
endorse what has already been decided. Austria's role as a non-permanent
member of the Security Council in the period of the last Gulf War is a
vivid example of this predicament.
Vis-à-vis the overwhelming factual power of the leading ("permanent")
actors in the Security Council, there is for the smaller states or even
regional groupings of states (such as the Arab League, the Organization
of African Unity, or the Organization of the Islamic Conference) no margin
to maneuver. This is particularly demonstrated by the peace process in
the Middle East, where, since 1967, no Security Council enforcement measures
have been imposed upon the occupying power in Palestine,7 while the authority
of the Council on the basis of Chapter VII was excessively used to pacify
the Islamic Gulf region with consequences that most of us are not yet aware
of.
We have seen that the present United Nations system reflects the power
balance of an earlier era and imposes upon the rest of the world a "legitimacy"
guaranteed by a few "constitutionally" privileged countries whereby such privilege results from actual power, not from legal rights.
Apart from this fact, the lack of democracy on the international level
is also evidenced by the United Nations' proven inability to do anything
meaningful to bridge the gap between North and South in terms of economic
conditions. The existing economic imbalances are not addressed by the UN
Charter, which is no wonder if we take into consideration the fact that
the Charter was drafted by the leading colonial powers of the forties.
The "constitutional inequality" which was written into the Charter
by those who privileged themselves as the "permanent members"
is complemented by the economic inequality between North and South. No
country of the South has the status of permanent member in the Security
Council. The "haves" are not ready to share with the "have-nots"
whether with regard to (political, military) power or wealth. The former
will therefore not accept any game rules on the basis of the principle
of equality as idealistically enunciated in the Preamble and in Chapter
I of the Charter.
Sovereign equality, in the legal sense of the term,8 is denied to the
non-permanent members of the Security Council; equality in a broader economic
and political sense is furthermore denied by the economically powerful
countries of the North to those of the South. Countermeasures proposed
by the UN General Assembly in the seventies see its 1974 declaration
on the establishment of a "New International Economic Order"9
have never been implemented.10 The global economic power rests in the hands
of the North, particularly of the so-called G7-states, three of which the
United States, the United Kingdom and France are permanent members of the
Security Council.
The global imbalance on the military level is even more serious: nuclear
power is mainly in the hands of the five permanent members of the Security
Council. This kind of military imbalance, related as it is to the possession
of arms of mass destruction, implies that most of the member states have
been made hostage to the power politics of the permanent members. There
is no freedom of decision and no margin for the exercise of national "sovereignty"
vis-à-vis the overwhelming destructive power of the nuclear states.
The events in connection with last year's extension of the Nuclear Non-proliferation
Treaty (NPT) are clear proof of this state of affairs.
The question we have to ask ourselves is how the international system
should be restructured so that these legal, economic, and military imbalances
will be eliminated and international organization will be based on the
rule of law, which alone can serve as the basis for transnational democracy.
How can democracy be achieved among UN member states in terms of legal
and constitutional procedures when huge economic and military imbalances
prevail? How can the concept of sovereign equality be the basis for the
international rule of law when the de facto sovereignty of the member states
is continuously eroded because of the above-described factual imbalances?11
Even if basic procedural rules of the UN Charter are changed, international
democracy cannot be achieved without addressing the drastic material inequalities
among states and groups of states. The North-South conflict can definitely
not serve as the framework for reshaping the decision-making procedures
of the United Nations along democratic lines.
This said, we now have to concentrate on the procedural aspects of transnational
democracy as the basis for United Nations reform. Our analysis is based
on the understanding that, just as the world organization cannot continue
to be the tool of the victorious powers of World War II, neither can it
be the instrument of the industrialized world in imposing its hegemony
upon the rest of the world. The paralysis which befell the organization
in the era of the East-West conflict must not be compensated now by the
use of the United Nations as a power tool in the hands of the only remaining
superpower and its allies or proxies. The question of transnational democracy
must be raised on the level of a "new world order" where no state
or group of states dominates the others. This idealistic assumption is
naturally the basis of all efforts toward a genuine democratic reform of
the international system within the framework of the United Nations.
(II)
The Requirements of Transnational
Democracy in a Multipolar System
Based on the Global Sharing of Power and Resources
The concept of democracy in the present global discourse is exclusively
used in the sense of representation. This relates more to an oligarchic
model than to the participatory system required by the universal validity
of human rights as the basis for any democratic system.12 In the present
ideological discourse dominated by the West, direct democracy is practically
excluded because of the assumption of its totalitarian nature. This is
in line with the special importance of pressure groups whether in the form
of political parties or other lobbies in the political mechanisms of the
so-called liberal democracies of the West.
The oligarchic (representative) paradigm of democracy best suits the
legitimization discourse of the "New World Order." Indeed, superpower
hegemony needs the fiction of representation for its legitimization.13
"Representation" unavoidably negates the sovereign status of
the citizen. In the history of the Western political system, it has functioned
as the classical ideological tool for the legitimization of élite
rule which, in the case of international relations, has been embodied by
the rule of the self-declared guardians of humanity over the rest of mankind.
This understanding of foreign policy excludes on the one hand the participation
of the citizen in the making of foreign policy in his own state; on the
other hand it excludes the smaller, "immature" states from the
participation in the decision-making processes on the global level of the
United Nations. In particular, the structure of the Security Council incorporates
this ideology of representation on the transnational level, whereby certain
states define their own role as the role of those who have "primary"
responsibility for the preservation of world peace (see the formulation
of Art. 24 of the Charter).
The procedural (decision-making) rules of the UN Security Council in
Art. 27 incorporate an extreme form of the ideology of representation.
The veto powers (the permanent members) fictitiously represent humankind
(the community of nations) with regard to the peoples' most basic rights,
such as the rights to life and peace.14
In order to make democratic rules applicable in an international framework,
the system of state representation as in the case of the UN General Assembly
and even more so of the Security Council would have to be complemented
or replaced by an Assembly of Peoples' Deputies (additional to or replacing
the General Assembly of states' representatives) who are directly elected
on the regional level. The Second International Conference On A More Democratic
United Nations (CAMDUN-2) has worked out specific proposals in this regard.15
There should be no illusion concerning the fact that the establishment
of such an additional body with special competence in the power equation
of the United Nations is not realistic in terms of the realities of power
politics. In view of Art. 108 any Charter amendment is totally elusive
if it is not in conformity with the wishes of the permanent members of
the Security Council. If, until now, it has not even been possible to abrogate
Art. 107 of the Charter (which clearly is a relic of World War II and,
in the present global constellation, grossly violates the spirit of peace,
co-operation and partnership that is to be promoted by the world organization
according to Chapter I of its Charter), how then could it be possible to
undertake the drastic steps of Charter amendment that are required in order
to do away with the privileged position of the "Great Five"
as incorporated in the veto right
that stands in the way of a genuine
democratization of the United Nations? In view of this situation, the scholar of
international affairs may only present the sketch of an ideal system, one that
could serve as an alternative to the present post-war system, knowing that the
question of implementation must be dealt with in another context.
Several proposals for United Nations reform have been made on the basis
of the present Charter, emphasizing the need to make better use of existing
provisions of the Charter itself. The Second International Conference On
A More Democratic United Nations (CAMDUN-2) in Vienna worked out a list
of nine specific proposals "that appear feasible under the UN Charter
as it exists," among them the proposal for the establishment of a
Second (peoples') Assembly which would constitute a subsidiary organ of
the General Assembly under Art. 22 and would be "representative of
the peoples of the United Nations as global inhabitants."16 Similar
proposals have been made by a Com-mission on Global Governance17 and by
other committees and think-tanks.18 These well-intentioned proposals sometimes
presented in a very cautious and conventional manner without challenging
the basic dogmas of present-day power politics are not sufficient when
it comes to a real democratization of the United Nations system. In most
cases, they amount to cosmetic measures because their implementation does
not affect the actual balance of power among the various organs of the
United Nations or the member states themselves. The proposal for a "Second
Assembly" of peoples' deputies also falls into this category as long
as such an assembly has no authority of its own in a system of checks and
balances that would have to be created anew. An advisory body may only
serve as an "ornament" representing such vague concepts as the
"conscience of the world," and it will not change the undemocratic
realities of decision-making within the UN.
Only through amending the Charter in some of its basic provisions
in regard to the power-sharing between General Assembly, Security Council
and International Court of Justice can one bring about an international
organization that conforms to basic principles of democracy. Such a Charter
reform should envisage an elaborate system of the separation of powers
that is comparable in structure to the commonly accepted requirements of
the rule of law on the domestic level of the member states. With regard
to democracy and legality the same rules should apply on the national and
on the transnational levels.19 The requirements of a separation of powers
may best be met by the introduction of a genuine two chamber-system in
the organization of the United Nations. While the General Assembly consists
of governmental representatives and makes its decisions on the basis of
the principle of "one stateone vote,"
a second chamber a Peoples' Assembly
should be created that would serve as the
legislative body of the organization. This assembly would consist of the
directly elected representatives of the world's population. Their number would
have to be related to the population size of the respective country or where
the country is too small to the population of a regional grouping that would
have to be created. The European Parliament could serve as a model for the
composition of such a parliamentary body on the global scale. While the General
Assembly in such a two chamber-system would be comparable to the Senate (second
chamber), the Peoples' Assembly would exercise an authority that is derived from
common democratic procedures. Its delegates would have to be elected in regular
intervals.
Ideally, such a parliamentary system of indirect democracy should be
complemented by forms of direct democracy worldwide referenda, for example when major issues of world peace are at stake. The question of the admissibility
of nuclear arms would be one such issue to be presented to the global population.
It remains to be seen to what extent the use of modern computer technology
can help to organize such direct decisions by the people.20 For the time
being, this is definitely beyond the scope of realization because of the
lack of the necessary infrastructure, particularly in the countries of
the South. Irrespective of this, referenda on major issues to be defined
by the International Peoples' Assembly (as it is envisaged here) could
be held in the member states of the United Nations according to common
procedural standards that are well established in all democratic countries.
Furthermore, if one aspires to establish genuine forms of direct democracy,
one may also consider defining the mandate of the peoples' deputies within
the framework of the imperative mandate.
It goes without saying that the introduction of such a new "parliamentary"
system in the UN is meaningless without an effective arrangement assuring
the separation of powers, particularly as concerns the Security Council.
Under the present Charter the Security Council embodies a kind of totalitarian
rule by the organization's founders over the rest of the member states.
The Council acts not only as executive power; its margin of discretion particularly in matters of international security
amounts to a kind
of legislative power insofar as it determines the rules of application
and even the norms of international law to be applied in the settlement
of disputes or in the preservation or restoration of world peace, while
at the same time it implicitly creates new norms through an application
practice that is often technically in violation of Charter norms. As recent
resolutions on Libya, former Yugoslavia and Sudan amply demonstrate, the
Council furthermore even acts as a judicial authority, i.e. it has arrogated
this authority in the absence of applicable Charter provisions. All of
this is to be viewed in a constitutional context in which the Council's
decisions are not subject to any review. The General Assembly in the present
system has no right at all to censure the Security Council or to recall
its members. It may only "consider" the Council's reports (as
stated in Art. 24, par. 3 of the Charter). The Council acts completely
arbitrarily in a "vacuum of power politics." It is clear to the
theoretician of democratic and constitutional procedures that the Security
Council must be integrated into a system of the separation of powers as
envisaged here; it must be assigned the role of an executive body that
must be held accountable to the peoples' delegates. If the world community
does not tackle this crucial issue of international legality and democracy,
we shall forever have a system of global anarchy where "might makes
right" and where a small minority rules over the rest of the world,
thus eternalizing present divisions and intensifying tensions along the
lines of the already existing North-South divide.21 International legitimacy,
however, can only be reached on the basis of democratic structures. No
"ideology of double standards" is acceptable, whereby democratic
standards are meant for domestic use (for application in the domestic constitutional
system) and the rules of power politics apply to the international realm.
The integration of the Security Council into a well-defined system of
checks and balances would inevitably erode the dogma of national sovereignty
in the sense of unlimited, unchecked state power whose exercise is beyond
any scrutiny on the part of the international community. It would at the
same time strengthen tendencies towards the transnational legality of a
"world state" or "world federation" structure. Sovereignty
in the sense of absolute state power is definitely not compatible with
the concept of equality required in any charter in which co-operation and
partnership for the common good i.e. economic and social development
and world peace prevail over "interests" exclusively defined
by power politics.
If the Security Council is to play a role in conformance with a new
system of checks and balances including the Peoples' Assembly (that in
fact would be the First Chamber in the system envisaged by us) and that
is compatible with the requirements of transnational democracy, its composition
would have to be balanced on a regional basis. The central executive body
of the global organization in charge of the preservation of world peace
cannot remain exclusively structured according to the interests of its
original founders. Apart from abolishing the veto privilege once and for
all,22 one also has to tackle the composition of its membership. As already
envisaged in Art. 23, par. 1 of the present Charter for the non-permanent
members, "equitable geographical distribution" should be the
principle for the selection of the state members. One should consider replacing
the concept of "permanent membership" with a kind of regional
membership. Seats on the Council would then be assigned to the various
regional political entities such as the European Union, the Organization
of African Unity, the Commonwealth of Independent States, the League of
Arab States, etc. Within each regional grouping the seat could rotate according
to a jointly approved scheme. This would prevent the kind of "over-representation"
which presently characterizes the Security Council system in favour of
the membership of European states.
The establishment of a global security structure comprising all member
states remains elusive under the present circumstances of national sovereignty
and power politics. The formation of more or less coherent regional power
structures on the basis of common economic and security interests seems
to be more realistic. The development of the European Union, the Association
of South-East Asian Nations (ASEAN), and the Gulf Co-operation Council
are examples of the emergence of such regional structures, in the framework
of which particularly smaller states may better be able to articulate their
legitimate interests and defend their international position. These regional
groupings are based on a certain homogeneity in their political and economic
systems; they have a concrete basis for their joint international action,
in contrast to "universal" organizations whose lack of internal
cohesiveness makes them prone to largely inefficient, often bureaucratic
action.
These regional groupings could constitute a new global system within
the framework of a reformed Security Council. The regional entities like
the "permanent members" in the old post-war system would constitute
a new Security Council on the basis of equal geographical distribution
and a shared responsibility for global affairs. No regional member should
be allowed to enjoy "constitutional" privileges. No such grouping
should be allowed to have overwhelming power over the others, as this would
profoundly destabilize the global order. (This is exactly the situation
we are witnessing today: the United States is practically the only actor
in the Security Council vis-à-vis member states which are economically
and militarily weak or otherwise marginalized.) The collective membership
on a regional basis which we envisage for a democratically reformed Council
would make such marginalization less likely. A system of multipolarity
with several regional power centers is definitely better suited for a kind
of democratic co-operation within the framework of the Security Council
than the present unipolar system in which every member state on its own
has to defend its national interests vis-à-vis the only superpower
that is able to enforce decisions on international peace and security.
This leads us to the question of power in the international system in
general. Even if a democratic reform of the United Nations Charter under
the present conditions of world economy and armaments were at all possible,
the overwhelming majority of member states would still not enjoy the freedom
of action that is necessary to make the exercise of one's democratic rights
meaningful. Democratic rules written down on paper would have to be based
on socio-economic and military realities, otherwise they remain abstract
procedures without applicability.23 The same holds true for the mechanisms
of democracy on the domestic level: de facto inequality in terms of economic
status or social standing etc. may prevent the citizen from making use
of specific rights he enjoys under the constitution. Similarly, a state
that depends on the goodwill of a rich and powerful member of the Security
Council, for example because its economy depends on foreign aid, because
its internal security is guaranteed by the security establishment of that
other state, and so on such a state has no freedom of decision, no margin
to maneuver when it comes to matters such as decisions on international
security that affect the interests of the more powerful state. The weaker
state's participation in Security Council deliberations and decisions becomes
democratically meaningless in such a context because that state cannot
make such decisions freely, as assumed by the Charter; it may even be dangerous
for the security, preservation of national sovereignty and economic interests
of that state if its decision contradicts the interests of more powerful
states. The recent record of Security Council resolutions since the Gulf
Crisis in 1990 gives ample proof of this. Erskine Childers referred to
this dilemma when he spoke of the Northern powers' "use of bribery
and extortion to silence" with the purpose to induce certain decisions
in the Security Council.24 For Childers, this behaviour of Security Council
member states "is the outright subversion of the very sovereignty
and equality of member states in international law at the United Nations."25
Legal equality remains an empty concept as long as gross inequalities exist
in terms of power politics, disparities which are related to the economic
and military status of each member state. This is one more argument in favour of our thesis that democratic decision-making in the Security Council
should be based on a regional representation in which the smaller state
enjoys the protection within the framework of the regional entity acting
on its behalf as a kind of "permanent" member of the Security
Council.
Without a minimum of fairness and balance in international economic
reality and in terms of international power politics in general, even the
most far-reaching democratic provisions in a reformed UN Charter would
be empty phrases or mere exhortations. The conventional theorists of international
politics usually overlook this harsh reality, which greatly damages the
credibility of their proposals. Without a kind of "new international
economic order"26 and without a "new international military order"
( in the sense of a certain balance in military strength ( transnational
democracy has no meaning at all. The formal exercise of such "democracy"
would only be a cover behind which to hide the real state of dependence
of most UN member states. Idealistic enunciations will not do away with
the harsh realities of international power politics, as should have become
clear, in the meantime, to all those who were originally taken by the rhetoric
of a "New World Order" in the post-Cold War euphoria. There is
no international democracy if one state (superpower) or a group of states
(e.g. the G7-members with regard to their economic wealth or the permanent
members of the Security Council with regard to their military superiority) hold
other states hostage to their strategies and interests.
These realities of power politics (representing an obstacle to the
exercise of transnational democracy) are particularly obvious in the military
field. Under the present conditions, the nuclear powers enjoy a certain
military and political strength that cannot be matched by the non-nuclear
states. The sovereignty of the latter is limited, even negated by the overwhelming
destructive potential of the nuclear states. It is obvious that no dialogue,
no democratic discourse is possible on the basis of such an imbalance in
terms of power politics, a situation in which one side can hold the others
hostage for the sake of its own interests. Democratic deliberations require
a certain balance of forces that allows each actor to express his views
without fear. However, the present inter-state discourse in the supreme
forum of the United Nations, the Security Council, is determined by fear
instilled by the great power(s) into the weaker states. Within a strictly
legal system even within the universal framework of the United Nations
no effective international control over these arms of mass destruction
can be envisaged. The overwhelming might of the nuclear states on the international
scene simply does not allow a formally "independent" international
body to be efficient in the exercise of its controlling power. The recent
developments in the relationship between the Security Council and the International
Court of Justice are further proof of this.27 Abolishing the arms of mass
destruction, above all nuclear arms, is therefore the basic condition for
democratic decision-making between states. This alone can ensure the necessary
balance in the interplay of forces on the transnational level. Such a measure
would undoubtedly be the largest contribution to the democratization of
the United Nations in terms of the conditions of realpolitik. It is within
this context that the "World Court Project" of the International
Association of Lawyers Against Nuclear Arms (IALANA), originally launched
by the late Seán MacBride in co-operation with the International
Progress Organization, gains special importance for the whole movement
to democratize the United Nations. The decision by the UN General Assembly
to ask the International Court of Justice for an advisory opinion on the
legality of the use of nuclear arms is a major step in this direction,
at least as far as international conscience-building is concerned.28 Furthermore,
it is high time that the Security Council came out with concrete plans
"for the establishment of a system for the regulation of armaments"
as called for in Art. 26 of the Charter. Such a system necessarily implies
a policy of disarmament based on the principle of the "least diversion
for armaments of the world's human and economic resources" as stated
in the same Article.
The question of military imbalances, which pose one of the biggest obstacles
to international democracy, leads us, however, to one of the most intractable
problems of international legality: that of enforcement. Granted that decisions
have been made in a genuinely democratic manner, there must be a coherent
international power structure that allows their implementation. In the
United Nations Organization of today, that is characterized by superpower
rule, enforcement is guaranteed by the permanent members of the Security
Council. The international rule of law in the sense of the application
of the Security Council's decisions or their imposition upon reluctant
member states depends exclusively upon the permanent members of the Council.
The Gulf War has demonstrated to the world what this actually means. In
the absence of a unified transnational power structure
even the agreements
stipulated in Art. 43 of the Charter for the establishment of a military
force under the control of the Security Council have never been concluded!29
the permanent members act as the sole guarantors of international peace
and "law enforcement." This is stipulated clearly in Art. 106,
part of the "Transitional Security Arrangements" of Chapter XVII,
in which "the parties to the Four-Nation Declaration, signed at Moscow,
30 October 1943 [!], and France" are authorized to act as guardians
of world security. Unavoidably, because of their veto privilege, this leads
to total arbitrariness in the enforcement of international law, whereby
the interests of the permanent members are the criterion for application
or non-application (a) of particular norms of international law and of
the UN Charter, and (b) of resolutions adopted by the Security Council
under Chapter VII.30 Thus, the rule of law becomes equivalent to the rule
of the strong.31 The maxim of "might makes right" replaces the
demand for the universal and unequivocal enforcement of international norms
even vis-à-vis the powerful international actors. This again forces
us to raise the question of national sovereignty, whose unrestricted exercise
in the form of superpower rule under the veto privilege implies the negation
of the other basic concept of the UN Charter, that of sovereign equality.
As far as cohesive and consistent "international law enforcement"
is concerned, sovereignty cannot be placed under a taboo any longer. Here,
too, we are confronted with the inevitability of a World State concept
(or that of a World Confederation) that does away with the traditional Souveränitätsanarchie, the "international anarchy among
sovereign actors."
Whatever the options for a reform of the present international system
may be, the dilemma of transnational law enforcement remains: the international
rule of law is either guaranteed by one superpower (or by a group of powers)
which necessarily leads to arbitrariness in the application of legal principles
and/or decisions; or the international rule of law is guaranteed by a community
of (legally) equal states i.e. through collective law enforcement within
a unified, democratic international structure which implies a lack of
efficiency in the implementation as long as the more powerful international
players cannot be easily brought to conform to decisions that affect their
own interests. This dilemma, that of the present system of collective security
within the framework of the United Nations, can only be solved on the basis
of a World State concept in which sovereignty is vested in the community
(the collective of world states) alone, which in turn derives this normative
status from the sovereignty of the citizen as a citizen of the world (a
cosmopolitan).32
Apart from the question of the (political, economic, military) power
of states, the international reality is determined by another factor that
is often overlooked in the treatises on the restructuring of international
organization: the factual power of transnational economic entities that
often determine the governments' bilateral and multilateral negotiations.
One of the weaknesses of the theory of "liberal democracy" in
the West is that these (not so hidden) economic players acting outside
the official governmental framework are often ignored. They have acquired
major importance at least for the shaping of North-South relations and
for the industrialized world's policies on international trade in general.
In spite of their actual influence, they act completely outside any framework
of transparent democratic procedures. Any reform of the international system
has to tackle this issue of hidden economic power and its leverage on transnational decision-making.
(III)
Summary: A "New World Order"
of Transnational Democracy versus the
"Old World Order" of Superpower Rule
What we have tried to describe here are the basic features of a "New
World Order" of transnational democracy as distinct from the "Old
World Order" of superpower rule. If the international community is
serious about the democratization of the United Nations, then one must
abandon the exclusionary character of the historical anti-Axis alliance
of the Second World War (which undoubtedly was of anti-totalitarian nature
and had its moral justification in the particular historical constellation)
in favour of a truly universal organization that encompasses all nations
and regions in fair and balanced representation. Only if the "We the
peoples" in the Charter's Preamble is taken seriously and if we distance
ourselves from the étatist paradigm of an absolutely posited national
sovereignty (as incorporated in the traditional concept of the nation-state)
will a new beginning be possible, in the sense of partnership and peaceful
co-operation.33 Inter-state democracy can only be based on such a reorientation
of the doctrine of international relations away from the assumptions of
the realist doctrine.34
In summing up our very provisional sketch of an alternative United Nations
system that revolves around the paradigm of transnational democracy, we
would like to point to the following basic requirements:
(A) The democratization of relations between states requires
a fundamental change in basic concepts of international law such as the
related concepts of national sovereignty and of interference in the internal
affairs of other states.35 Sovereignty, which in its traditional étatist
conception is linked to an abstract state entity, makes the existing imbalances
we have referred to here even larger and makes democratic partnership between
states even more elusive. Sovereignty must be redefined with regard to
the sovereign rights of the citizen that are the foundation of every legitimate
political entity.
Acknowledging this is the only way to democratically solve the problem
of inequality of sovereign member states of the United Nations, in which
one state represents the interests of one thousand citizens and another
state represents the interests of one billion, but in which both presently
enjoy the same one vote in the General Assembly of UN member states. In
the present imbalanced situation in the UN system, this amounts to a kind
of discrimination, i.e. of "weighted voting" in the form of the
one state-one vote formula, in favour of the less populated states and
at the expense of the vast majority of mankind. This inequality, that particularly
intensifies the tensions between the countries of the North and of the
South, has to be compensated as we propose in this brief sketch of genuine
democratic reform through a kind of weighted voting-formula which takes
into account the population size of each member state.36 (As we stated
earlier, the present General Assembly fits into the new system only as
a Second Chamber in the form of a Senate, granting minority representation
to the smaller states.) The normative requirements of such "weighted
voting" in the international decision-making bodies can best be administered
(as we have outlined above):
(a)
through a balanced regional representation in the Security
Council (whereby the seats allocated to each region on a permanent basis
rotate among the members of the regional group), and
(b) through the establishment of an International Peoples' Assembly
as the First Chamber in this new UN system. In this First Chamber, which
would be similar in structure and competence to the European Parliament,
the number of deputies of each country or group of countries in the case
of smaller states would be proportional to the actual population size.
The protection of "minority rights" of smaller states can best
be assured in such a system with a two-chamber model, whereby the General
Assembly would serve as the Second Chamber.
(B) The democratization of relations between states requires
the introduction of a genuine separation of powers between the two envisaged
world chambers which together comprise "legislative" authority,
the executive power represented by the Security Council, and the judicial
authority represented by the World Court. A new democratic Charter of the
United Nations would have to define the role of the "International
Peoples' Assembly" the First Chamber
in such a way that basic
competencies presently reserved for the Security Council would be given
to the peoples' delegates. It would be totally impossible to simply transfer
the role and competencies of the presently existing General Assembly to
such a new Peoples' Assembly. Such an Assembly should above all be able
to pass resolutions that are binding upon all member states (including
the members of the Security Council), whereby the Council's role would
be to enforce these resolutions. The authoritarian
and in a certain sense
even totalitarian structure of the present Security Council, in which
legislative, executive and judiciary powers de facto coincide, cannot be
tolerated in an alternative international system based on the paradigm
of democracy. The dangerous development in the present "new"
world order results precisely from this lack of the separation of powers
in the UN system, in which the Security Council since the collapse of
the bipolar power system of the post-war era has arrogated more and more
powers on behalf of its leading actor, the United States.
I am well aware that this sketch of a democratic alternative to the
present United Nations is only an idealistic vision far removed from reality.
The biggest obstacle to the achievement of this alternative
apart from
the interest for the preservation of power on the part of the big economic,
military and political conglomerates in the form of the nation states,
transnational corporations etc. is the lack of cosmopolitan consciousness.
As long as we exclusively define ourselves our identity
on the basis
of ethnic, religious, and national affiliations, there will be no understanding
for an all-pervasive transnational order which alone can be the framework
for international democracy. Our education towards transnational (cosmopolitan)
solidarity and "global nation-building" still has a long way
to go.37
With regard to the United Nations Organization, the question arises
for the philosophical analyst whether a system as described above in terms
of superpower hegemony and the absolute sovereignty of the nation state
can be reformed at all, or whether it should be replaced by an alternative
system based on another paradigm of international organization: that of
democracy instead of power and interest politics. The provisions of the
Charter exclude any amendments without the consent of the permanent members
of the Security Council, which makes democratic reform impossible in terms
of realpolitik. The principal question still remains for those who proclaim
the goal of United Nations reform: should a transnational system of decision-making
be based on the paradigm of superpower representation (which is the reality
of the United Nations in spite of the idealistic rhetoric of the Charter's
Preamble), which practically legitimizes power politics in its unrestrained
form, or should such a transnational system be based on the paradigm of
democracy? The latter would imply not only a drastic change of basic concepts
of international law, but also a shift in the balance of power from the
present uni-polar to a genuinely multi-polar (not bi-polar) system in which
all the regions could articulate their specific interests and concerns
on an equal basis.
If the present international system is not able to accommodate the increasing
concerns of the large majority of nations about the instrumentalization
of the United Nations Organization for the economic and strategic interests
of the at present
only superpower and its allies, and if the United
Nations continues to become a "party to the conflict" along the
lines of the newly emerging North-South bipolarity, then the world organization,
missing its stated goal of universality and instead favouring partisanship
and great power interests, may well meet the same fate as its predecessor,
the League of Nations.
Endnotes
-
See
Declaration of Legal Experts on UN Sanctions Against Libya. New York,
1 December 1994 (Records of the International Progress Organization) and
point 8 of the Memorandum on the Dispute between Libya and Members of the
Security Council over the Inquiries into the Bombings of Civilian Airliners.
International Progress Organization: New York, 6 February 1992.
-
General Assembly resolution 377 (V) of 3 November 1950 states "that
failure of the Security Council to discharge its responsibilities ...,
does not relieve Member States of their obligations" and stipulates
that "if the Security Council ... fails to exercise its primary responsibility
..., the General Assembly shall consider the matter immediately with a
view to making appropriate recommendations to Members for collective measures
... to maintain and restore international peace and security."
-
See the messages of the International Progress Organization of 19 December
1990 and 19 January 1991 to the President of the Security Council.
-
Cf. the author's analysis in
The Voting Procedure in the UN Security
Council. Examining a Normative Contradiction in the UN Charter and its
Consequences on International Relations. International Progress Organization:
Vienna, 1991.
-
For more details, see the author's paper
Democracy and the New World
Order. International Progress Organization: Vienna, 1993.
-
See the author's analysis:
The United Nations Sanctions Policy and International
Law. Just World Trust: Penang (Malaysia), 1995.
-
See Hans Köchler (ed.),
The Human Rights Situation in Palestine.
Reports by the Delegations of Inquiry on Behalf of the International Committee
for Palestinian Human Rights. International Progress Organization: Vienna,
1989.
-
For details see Aleksandar
Magaraević, "The Sovereign Equality
of States," in Milan Sahović (ed.),
Principles of International Law
Concerning Friendly Relations and Cooperation. Belgrade, 1972, pp. 179-218.
-
See also the
Declaration on the Right to Development (General Assembly
resolution 97 [XLI] of 4 December 1986).
-
See Nassau Adams, "The UN's neglected brief. 'The advancement of
all peoples'?" in Erskine Childers (ed.),
Challenges to the United
Nations. Building a safer world. Catholic Institute for International Relations:
London, 1994/New York, 1995, pp. 26-50.
-
See Robert Charvin, "Egalité et inegalité devant la loi
internationale":
Les cahiers de Nord-Sud XXI, No. 2 [Geneva, 1994]. Boutros
Boutros-Ghali even speaks of a "relative" juridical equality
of states and their "functional" inequality with regard to their
factual-political inequality. See "Le principe d'égalité
des États et les organisations internationales," in
Recueil
des Cours. Académie de droit internationale, vol. 100 (1960), II,
pp. 30ff.
-
See the author's analysis in
Democracy and Human Rights. Do Human Rights
Concur With Particular Democratic Systems? International Progress Organization:
Vienna, 1990.
-
"Representation" in the sense of a special responsibility
of the superpower(s) for world peace and security, combined with an authority
to act on behalf of all the others (as stipulated by the Charter's description
of the Security Council's function in Art. 24, par. 1).
-
See the author's
The Voting Procedure in the United Nations Security
Council, esp. Chapter III: The veto privilege as the major impediment to
the achievement of collective security, pp. 13ff.
-
For details see Hans Köchler (ed.),
The United Nations and the
New World Order. Keynote addresses from the Second International Conference
On A More Democratic United Nations. International Progress Organization:
Vienna, 1992. Cf. esp. Concluding Statement of the Second International
Conference On A More Democratic United Nations, pp. 49-52. See also the
proposal for a "United Nations Parliamentary Assembly" in Erskine
Childers with Brian Urquhart, Renewing the United Nations System. Uppsala,
1994, pp. 212-213.
-
See Hans Köchler (ed.),
The United Nations and the New World Order,
p. 50.
-
See
Our Global Neighborhood. The report of the Commission on Global
Governance. Oxford University Press: Oxford/New York, 1995.
-
See, for example,
The United Nations in its Second Half-Century. A Report
of the Independent Working Group on the Future of the United Nations. Yale
University Printing Service, no date.
-
See the analysis by the former Foreign Minister and Head of State of
Austria, Rudolf Kirchschläger: "Ethik und Außenpolitik,"
in Hans Köchler (ed.),
Philosophie und Politik. Dokumentation eines
interdisziplinären Seminars. Arbeitsgemeinschaft für Wissenschaft
und Politik: Innsbruck, 1973, pp. 69-74.
-
See Geoffrey Darnton, "The Architecture of Large-scale and International
Participative Democracy," in Hans Köchler (ed.),
The Crisis of
Representative Democracy. Peter Lang: Frankfurt/Bern/New York, 1987, pp.
263-283.
-
See Erskine Childers, "The Demand for Equity and Equality: The
North-South Divide in the United Nations," in Hans Köchler (ed.),
The United Nations and International Democracy. Jamahir Society for Culture
and Philosophy: Vienna, 1995, pp. 17-36.
-
See the author's proposals in
The Voting Procedure in the United Nations
Security Council, esp. pp. 41ff.
-
See Ahmed Abdalla, "Unequal sovereignty, unequal power," in
Al-Ahram Weekly, 19-25 January 1995, p. 11.
-
"The Demand for Equity and Equality: The North-South Divide in
the United Nations," p. 32.
-
Op. cit., p. 33.
-
See Hans Köchler (ed.),
The New International Economic Order. Philosophical
and Socio-cultural Implications. Guildford Educational Press: Guildford,
1980.
-
For more details see the author's reference in
The United Nations Sanctions
Policy and International Law. Just World Trust: Penang, 1995, p. 10 and
footnote 52.
-
See "Nuclear Weapons In Court. A Dream Becomes Reality":
World Court Project Report. Lawyers' Committee on Nuclear Policy: New
York, Winter 1995.
-
Par. 3 of Art. 43 calls since 1945! for the negotiation of such agreements
"as soon as possible."
-
See the author's analysis:
The Voting Procedure in the United Nations
Security Council, Chapter I:
"The voting procedure in the UN Security Council
and traditional power politics," pp. 5ff.
-
With regard to US foreign policy see the pertinent analysis of Francis
Anthony Boyle, "Machiavellianism Destroys Constitutionalism,"
in his work World Politics and International Law. Durham, 1985, pp. 293ff.
-
See the author's considerations in "The Principles of International
Law and Human Rights," in
Democracy and the International Rule of
Law. Propositions for an Alternative World Order. Selected Papers Published
on the Occasion of the Fiftieth Anniversary of the United Nations. Springer:
Vienna/New York, 1995, esp. pp. 74ff.
-
An idealistic vision of "world government" in this sense is
presented in the Constitution for the Federation of Earth adopted at the
1977 session of the "World Constituent Assembly" in Innsbruck
and revised at the 1991 session at the initiative of the "World Constitution
and Parliament Association." See
A Constitution for the Federation
of Earth. Lakewood/Colorado [1991].
-
For a detailed description of this influential doctrine of international
relations see Hans J. Morgenthau,
Politics Among Nations. The Struggle
for Power and Peace. New York, 5th ed. 1978. See also the author's analysis:
Foreign Policy and Democracy. Reconsidering the Universality of the Democratic
Principles. International Progress Organization: Vienna, 1988.
-
The concept of sovereignty has to be further rethought with regard to
the transboundary impact of measures affecting the environment. See the
inaugural speech of the Austrian Head of State before the Tenth General
Conference of Austrian Jurists (Vienna, 12 September 1989) where he called
for the replacement of national "solipsism", based on the absolute
concept of state sovereignty, by a model of partnership in international
relations.
-
See also H. Newcombe, J. Wert, A. Newcombe,
Comparison of Weighted Voting
Formulas for the United Nations. Preprint. Peace Research Institute: Dundas/Ont.,
1970.
-
See our analysis in "The Concept of the Nation and the Question
of Nationalism. The Traditional 'Nation State' Versus a Multicultural 'Community
State'," in Michael Dunne and Tiziano Bonazzi (eds.),
Citizenship
and Rights in Multicultural Societies. Keele, 1995, pp. 44-51.
|